What is it about?
Imagine someone being pricked with a needle or burned, but instead of wincing in pain, they laugh or calmly stretch out their hand for more. This unusual reaction occurs in a rare condition called pain asymbolia (PA), where people respond strangely to painful stimuli. While they might recognize something as "painful," they don’t seem to suffer or feel bothered by it. For years, scientists and philosophers have debated what’s really happening in PA. Are these individuals truly feeling pain but missing the emotional reaction? Or is something entirely different going on? The standard explanation suggests that people with PA do feel pain, but it’s “pain without painfulness.” For example, they might sense the sharp prick of a needle but don’t experience the unpleasantness or urgency to avoid it. This explanation has been widely accepted to support the idea that pain has multiple components—such as the raw sensation of injury, the unpleasant emotional experience, and the drive to protect oneself. Griffith and Kind, the authors of this paper, challenge this explanation. They argue that the evidence doesn’t convincingly show that PA involves actual pain. For one, the reactions of people with PA vary widely—some laugh, some deny feeling pain entirely, and others appear indifferent. Additionally, many people with PA have other neurological issues, such as difficulties with language or memory, which could explain their unusual responses without requiring the label of “pain.” The authors also point out that calling PA a form of pain leads to contradictions. For example, if pain is supposed to be complex (having multiple psychological components) and PA is a case in that only one of these components (the sensation) is present, how can PA itself be pain? Making this claim undermines the very idea that should be established! Philosophers who insist that PA is pain end up confusing themselves and others, claiming that pain is both complex and simple at the same time—a logical contradiction. Instead, Griffith and Kind argue that PA isn’t a type of pain at all. They suggest it’s more likely a symptom of other neurological issues, like a side effect, rather than its own standalone condition. They call for further research to better understand PA and its connections to other disorders. If this is true, it means that PA does not provide evidence for the idea that pain is a complex phenomenon. Griffith and Kind aren’t dismissing PA—they believe it’s a fascinating phenomenon that deserves study. But they argue that until we know more, it’s premature to use PA as a cornerstone in debates about pain. Instead of jumping to conclusions, they urge a more cautious, evidence-based approach to this puzzling condition.
Featured Image
Photo by Tao Yuan on Unsplash
Why is it important?
This debate extends beyond just one rare condition. Philosophers often use pain asymbolia (PA) to explore the nature of pain itself. More specifically, they have used it to argue that pain is a complex phenomenon with multiple components, not just a sensation. PA was thought to support this idea because it appears to show that some components of pain can exist without others. However, if PA isn’t actually a form of pain, it fundamentally changes how these debates progress. Pain asymbolia can no longer serve as evidence for the idea that pain is a complex entity.
Perspectives
Read the Original
This page is a summary of: Pain Asymbolia is Not Pain, Philosophy of Science, December 2023, Cambridge University Press,
DOI: 10.1017/psa.2023.167.
You can read the full text:
Contributors
The following have contributed to this page